페이지 이미지
PDF
ePub

BOOK 1. extend this right of inspection so far as to lay a restraint on CHAP. XX. his subjects in the administration of their affairs-which would be no less injurious to the true welfare of the state than to the just liberty of the citizens. The particulars of this subject belong to public law and politics.

? 255. The

may subject

it to regula

tions of po

lice.

It must also be observed, that individuals are not so perSovereign fectly free in the economy or government of their affairs as not to be subject to the laws and regulations of police made by the sovereign. For instance, if vineyards are multiplied to too great an extent in a country which is in want of corn, the sovereign may forbid the planting of the vine in fields. proper for tillage; for here the public welfare and the safety of the state are concerned. When a reason of such importance requires it, the sovereign or the magistrate may oblige [116] an individual to sell all the provisions in his possession above what are necessary for the subsistence of his family, and may fix the price he shall receive for them. (66) The public authority may and ought to hinder monopolies, and suppress all practices tending to raise the price of provisions—to which practices the Romans applied the expressions annonam incendere, comprimere, vexare.

2256. In

Every man may naturally choose the person to whom he heritances. would leave his property after his death, as long as his right is not limited by some indispensable obligation-as, for instance, that of providing for the subsistence of his children. (67) The children also have naturally a right to inherit their father's property in equal proportions. But this is no reason why particular laws may not be established in a state, with regard to testaments and inheritances-a respect being, however, paid to the essential laws of nature. Thus, by a rule established in many places with a view to support noble families, the eldest son is, of right, his father's principal heir. Lands perpetually appropriated to the eldest male heir of a family, belong to him by virtue of another right, which has its source in the will of the person who, being sole owner of those lands, has bequeathed them in that manner.

(66) In Great Britain no such interference now takes place, though formerly it was exercised. See 1 Bla. Com. 287.-C.

(67) In England a parent has an absolute right to devise or bequeath all his property to a stranger in exclusion of

his children.

192

BOOK L

CHAP. XXI.

CHAP. XXI.

OF THE ALIENATION OF THE PUBLIC PROPERTY, OR THE
DOMAIN, AND THAT OF A PART OF THE STATE.

alienate its

public pro

THE nation, being the sole mistress of the property in her a 257. The possession, may dispose of it as she thinks proper, and may nation may lawfully alienate or mortgage it. This right is a necessary consequence of the full and absolute domain: the exercise perty. of it is restrained by the law of nature only with respect to proprietors who have not the use of reason necessary for the management of their affairs; which is not the case with a nation. Those who think otherwise, cannot allege any solid reason for their opinion; and it would follow from their principles that no safe contract can be entered into with any nation;-a conclusion which attacks the foundation of all public treaties.

respect.

But it is very just to say, that the nation ought carefully & 258. Duto preserve her public property-to make a proper use of ties of a nait-not to dispose of it without good reasons, nor to alienate tion in this or mortgage it but for a manifest public advantage, or in case of a pressing necessity. This is an evident consequence of the duties a nation owes to herself. The public property is extremely useful and even necessary to the nation; and she cannot squander it improperly without injuring herself, and shamefully neglecting the duty of self-preservation. I speak of the public property, strictly so called, or the domain of the state. Alienating its revenues is cutting the sinews of government. As to the property common to all the citizens, the nation does an injury to those who derive advantage from it, if she alienates it without necessity, or without cogent [117] reasons. She has a right to do this as proprietor of these possessions; but she ought not to dispose of them except in a manner that is consistent with the duties which the body owes to its members.

The same duties lie on the prince, the director of the na- 2 259. Dution: he ought to watch over the preservation and prudent ties of the management of the public property-to stop and prevent prince. all waste of it-and not suffer it to be applied to improper

uses.

?

public pro

perty.

The prince, or the superior of the society, whatever he is, 260. He being naturally no more than the administrator, and not the cannot proprietor of the state, his authority, as sovereign or head of alienate the the nation, does not of itself give him a right to alienate or mortgage the public property. The general rule then is, that the superior cannot dispose of the public property, as to its substance the right to do this being reserved to the proprietor alone, since proprietorship is defined to be the right to dispose

BOOK I

of a thing substantially. If the superior exceeds his powers CHAP. XXI. with respect to this property, the alienation he makes of it will be invalid, and may at any time be revoked by his successor, or by the nation. This is the law generally received in France; and it was upon this principle that the duke of Sully* advised Henry IV. to resume the possession of all the domains of the crown alienated by his predecessors.

$261. The nation may

give him a

right to it.

$261. Rules

spect to

The nation, having the free disposal of all the property belonging to her (§ 257), may convey her right to the sovereign, and consequently confer upon him that of alienating and mortgaging the public property. But this right not being necessary to the conductor of the state, to enable him to render the people happy by his government-it is not to be presumed that the nation have given it to him; and, if they have not made an express law for that purpose, we are to conclude that the prince is not invested with it, unless he has received full, unlimited, and absolute authority.

The rules we have just established relate to alienations of on this sub- public property in favour of individuals. The question assumes ject with re- a different aspect when it relates to alienations made by one treaties be- nation to another:† it requires other principles to decide it in the different cases that may present themselves. Let us endeavour to give a general theory of them.

tween na

tion and nation.

1. It is necessary that nations should be able to treat and contract validly with each other, since they would otherwise find it impossible to bring their affairs to an issue, or to obtain the blessings of peace with any degree of certainty. Whence it follows, that, when a nation has ceded any part of its property to another, the cession ought to be deemed valid and [118] irrevocable, as in fact it is, in virtue of the notion of property. This principle cannot be shaken by any fundamental law by which a nation might pretend to deprive themselves of the power of alienating what belongs to them: for, this would be depriving themselves of all power to form contracts with other nations, or attempting to deceive them. A nation with such a law ought never to treat concerning its property: if it is obliged to it by necessity, or determined to do it for its own advantage, the moment it broaches a treaty on the subject, it renounces its fundamental law. It is seldom disputed that an entire nation may alienate what belongs to itself: but it is asked, whether its conductor, its sovereign, has this power? The question may be determined by the fundamental laws. But, if the laws say nothing on this subject, then we have recourse to our second principle, viz.

2. If the nation has conferred the full sovereignty on its conductor-if it has intrusted to him the care, and, without

See his Memoirs.

† Quod domania regnorum inalienabilia et semper revocabilia dicuntur, id respectu privatorum intelligitur; nam

contra alias gentes divino privilegio opus foret. Leibnitz, Præfat, ad Cod. Jur. Gent. Diplomat.

reserve, given him the right, of treating and contracting with BOOK I. other states, it is considered as having invested him with all CHAP. XXI. the powers necessary to make a valid contract. The prince is then the organ of the nation: what he does is considered as the act of the nation itself; and, though he is not the owner of the public property, his alienations of it are valid, as being duly authorized.

state.

The question becomes more distinct, when it relates, not to §263. Alienthe alienation of some parts of the public property, but to ation of a the dismembering of the nation or state itself the cession part of the of a town or a province that constitutes a part of it. This question, however, admits of a sound decision on the same principles. A nation ought to preserve itself (§ 26)—it ought to preserve all its members-it cannot abandon them; and it is under an engagement to support them in their rank as members of the nation (§ 17). It has not, then, a right to traffic with their rank and liberty, on account of any advantages it may expect to derive from such a negotiation. They have joined the society for the purpose of being members of it— they submit to the authority of the state for the purpose of promoting in concert their common welfare and safety, and not of being at its disposal, like a farm or a herd of cattle. But the nation may lawfully abandon them in a case of extreme necessity; and she has a right to cut them off from the body, if the public safety requires it. When, therefore, in such a case, the state gives up a town or a province to a neighbour or to a powerful enemy, the cession ought to remain valid as to the state, since she had a right to make it: nor can she any longer lay claim to the town or province thus alienated, since she has relinquished every right she could have over it.

the dismembered party.

But the province or town thus abandoned and dismembered $ 264. from the state, is not obliged to receive the new master whom Rights of the state attempts to set over it. Being separated from the society of which it was a member, it resumes all its original rights; and if it be capable of defending its liberty against the prince who would subject it to his authority, it may lawfully resist him. Francis I. having engaged, by the treaty [119] of Madrid, to cede the duchy of Burgundy to the emperor Charles V., the states of that province declared, "that, having never been subject but to the crown of France, they would die subject to it; and that, if the king abandoned them, they would take up arms, and endeavour to set themselves at liberty, rather than pass into a new state of subjection."* It is true, subjects are seldom able to make resistance on such occasions; and, in general, their wisest plan will be to submit to their new master, and endeavour to obtain the best terms they can.

* Mezeray's History of France, vol. ii. p. 458.

BOOK I.

$ 265. Whether

ber the

Has the prince, or the superior of whatever kind, a power CHAP. XXI. to dismember the state? We answer as we have done with respect to the domain:-if the fundamental laws forbid all dismemberment by the sovereign, he cannot do it without the the prince concurrence of the nation or its representatives. But, if the has power laws are silent, and if the prince has received a full and abto dismem- solute authority, he is then the depositary of the rights of the nation, and the organ by which it declares its will. The na tion ought never to abandon its members but in a case of necessity, or with a view to the public safety, and to preserve itself from total ruin; and the prince ought not to give them up except for the same reasons. But, since he has received an absolute authority, it belongs to him to judge of the necessity of the case, and of what the safety of the state requires.

state.

On occasion of the above-mentioned treaty of Madrid, the principal persons in France, assembled at Cognag after the king's return, unanimously resolved, "that his authority did not extend so far as to dismember the crown.”* The treaty was declared void, as being contrary to the fundamental law of the kingdom: and, indeed, it had been concluded without sufficient powers: for, as the laws in express terms refused to the king the power of dismembering the kingdom, the concurrence of the nation was necessary for that purpose; and it might give its consent by the medium of the states-general. Charles V. ought not to have released his prisoner before those very states had approved the treaty; or rather, making a more generous use of his victory, he should have imposed less rigorous conditions, such as Francis I. would have beer. able to comply with, and such as he could not, without dishonour, have refused to perform. But now that there are no longer any meetings of the states-general in France, the king remains the sole organ of the state, with respect to other powers these latter have a right to take his will for that of all France; and the cessions the king might make them would remain valid, in virtue of the tacit consent by which the nation has vested the king with unlimited powers to treat with them. Were it otherwise, no solid treaty could be entered into with the crown of France. For greater security, [120] however, other powers have often required that their treaties should be registered in the parliament of Paris; but at present even this formality seems to be laid aside.

* Mezeray's History of France, vol. ii. p. 458.

« 이전계속 »